Group Details Private

Global Moderators

Forum wide moderators

  • RE: STLR - Score Than Leveled Runoff might not be too complex for voters

    @gregw said in STLR - Score Than Leveled Runoff might not be too complex for voters:

    @toby-pereira said in STLR - Score Than Leveled Runoff might not be too complex for voters:

    Using score ratios is always a bad idea. It only makes sense (as with utility scores) to look at the absolute difference between scores. If someone scores three candidates 0, 1, 2, then they are equidistant. To see the 1 as infinitely more than the 0 is bad voting method behaviour.
    It would also be insane if (under a 0 to 5 ballot) if someone scoring two candidates 5 and 1 had less voting power in the run-off than someone scoring them 1 and 0.

    Therefore, STLR’s leveled runoff is not a good idea, but it might be less bad using a 1 - 6 scoring range than a 0 - 5 range. Also, normalizing a ballot with scores of 4, 2, 1, and 0 to scores of 5, 3, 2, and 1, keeping the absolute differences, makes more sense. Call it STLR2? It would be a little easier to explain the regular STLR. Thank you for the help!

    Well, if I was normalising, I would always stretch scores to fill the whole range. So every voter would have a 0 and a 5 in this case.

    posted in Single-winner
  • RE: Variable house sizes

    @lime said in Variable house sizes:

    @toby-pereira said in Variable house sizes:

    Also, looking at proportional voting methods rather than apportionment (which is more relevant if we're talking about the Holy Grail of cardinal PR), some countries are split into regions where they might each have 5 or so representatives elected (normally using STV). We would not be able to reduce this number in a particular region if doing so would give a more proportional result, because it would mean the entire region would be be under-represented nationally.

    There's two reasons I still think this question would be relevant:

    1. In some cases, there's more flexibility (if nothing else, small committees like city councils).
    2. Even if we have to accept a fixed-size legislature, proving a method satisfies the core in the variable-size case would probably imply a nearly-satisfied core property in the case of a fixed-size legislature (think of how Webster satisfies lower quota 99.9% of the time). It could also lead to randomized methods that can satisfy the core with a bare minimum of randomness (requiring random selection or weighting only very, very rarely).

    Also if we're using a candidate-based system (e.g. STV or a cardinal method as opposed to party list), it wouldn't make sense to talk about parties being over-represented since candidates would be elected in a party-agnostic manner. So to talk of quota violations would become meaningless.

    Thus why I asked about whether we could guarantee the core instead, which seems like the most attractive generalization of quota for me. (As well as having very appealing strategy-resistance properties).

    Methods that guarantee core stability are of interest to me (see this thread, which I linked to earlier) even if it's not my priority. From what I've read, I think it's still unproven that it's guaranteed that the core is non-empty. But if you use a stability measure (as suggested in the thread) rather than an all-or-nothing, it could be workable regardless.

    posted in Proportional Representation
  • RE: Variable house sizes

    @lime said in Variable house sizes:

    @toby-pereira said in Variable house sizes:

    In your example, allocating the extra seat wouldn't violate either of these (I don't think divisor methods fail population monotonicity anyway). With 399, 101 and 100, the (almost) exact number of seats each with 7 to elect would be 4.655, 1.178 and 1.167. So the 399 getting 4 or 5 wouldn't violate quota and neither would the others getting 1 or 2.

    Ack, I botched the example. Here's an example from Balinski and Young that illustrates the example better. The problem with satisfying quota in this example is it would require having some states be dramatically over (or under) represented.

    6046f5ed-7c3a-4b17-a328-4f3334df4729-image.png

    @toby-pereira said in Variable house sizes:

    Obviously, I understand that having just the 6 seats would give better proportionality, but without any specific violations, where do you draw the line of how many seats to remove? If 8 was the highest available available number to give, would you still cut it down to 6 for better proportionality? Or what if the proportions were pretty much exactly 3/7, 2/7, 2/7, and you could give a theoretical maximum of 13 seats. Would you cut it all the way down to 7?

    In the party-list apportionment case, the line-in-the-sand gets drawn at exactly half the number of parties, which is the most the initial apportionment can be off by, and the worst-case difference between Webster and Hamilton. In practice, the actual is ~0.

    Do you think a method not violating quota is a matter of principle or simply that it looks better if it doesn't? Because interestingly enough, while Hamilton doesn't violate quota, Webster is simply Hamilton but without the IIB failures. For two parties they are identical.

    If you take your example above where D is below the lower quota under Webster, you can do a Hamilton comparison between D and any of the others head-to-head and the result won't change.

    E.g. compare A and D. They won 27 seats between them under Webster. Of those 27, A should now have 1.508 seats and D should have 25.492. So it is better for A to keep the 2nd seat rather than D get the 26th under both Hamilton and Webster. The same would apply if you compared D against either B or C.

    This is why I regard occasional quota violations as a natural proportional result not requiring a change in house size even if it might look unfair at a first glance.

    posted in Proportional Representation
  • RE: Variable house sizes

    @lime said in Variable house sizes:

    I consider any rule that violates either quota or population monotonicity to be unfair; instead I reject the assumption (usually left unstated) that we must have a fixed number of seats with equally-weighted representatives. (Why?)

    In your example, allocating the extra seat wouldn't violate either of these (I don't think divisor methods fail population monotonicity anyway). With 399, 101 and 100, the (almost) exact number of seats each with 7 to elect would be 4.655, 1.178 and 1.167. So the 399 getting 4 or 5 wouldn't violate quota and neither would the others getting 1 or 2.

    Both Webster and Jefferson would give the 399 the extra seat. Obviously, I understand that having just the 6 seats would give better proportionality, but without any specific violations, where do you draw the line of how many seats to remove? If 8 was the highest available available number to give, would you still cut it down to 6 for better proportionality? Or what if the proportions were pretty much exactly 3/7, 2/7, 2/7, and you could give a theoretical maximum of 13 seats. Would you cut it all the way down to 7?

    This could also lead to another sort of paradox - a state's population could increase and they lose a seat, because due to a more proportional result becoming available, every state loses seats.

    Also, looking at proportional voting methods rather than apportionment (which is more relevant if we're talking about the Holy Grail of cardinal PR), some countries are split into regions where they might each have 5 or so representatives elected (normally using STV). We would not be able to reduce this number in a particular region if doing so would give a more proportional result, because it would mean the entire region would be be under-represented nationally. Also if we're using a candidate-based system (e.g. STV or a cardinal method as opposed to party list), it wouldn't make sense to talk about parties being over-represented since candidates would be elected in a party-agnostic manner. So to talk of quota violations would become meaningless.

    So I think the proportionality criteria you want really only apply to apportionment and nationwide party-list voting. It doesn't apply to candidate-based voting or the Holy Grail of cardinal PR (which you wouldn't use for apportionment). I know this thread started as an apportionment thing, but since cardinal PR came up, I think all this has become relevant.

    posted in Proportional Representation
  • RE: Variable house sizes

    @lime Cardinal PR and Holy Grail criteria is my main area of interest when it comes to voting methods, so any mention of them and I'm back in the thread.

    Your criteria aren't the same that I would pick. There was also some discussion in this thread, but Sainte-Laguë/Webster does not pass core stability or priceability. I (along with many other people) would consider it to be the most accurate party PR method, so if a cardinal method reduces to Sainte-Laguë/Webster where there is party voting, it should not be disqualified.

    As I understand it, D'Hondt is the only divisor method that satisfies lower quota, so therefore the only one in the running to pass core stability. As I also understand it, non-divisor methods all fail Independence of Irrelevant Ballots, so I think we would be forced into a method that reduces to D'Hondt under party voting if we also wanted to pass that, which isn't satisfactory.

    It is an inconvenient truth actually that most PR criteria that have popped up in recent years for cardinal methods are failed by Sainte-Laguë/Webster, so I would argue that they are not really fit for purpose.

    Single-candidate Pareto efficiency is pretty non-controversial. If candidate A is approved on all the ballots that B is and at least one other, then if B is elected so should A.

    However, the multiple-candidate criterion, while intuitive, is at least debatable. Basically: for the winning set of candidates, there should not be another set for which every voter has approved at least as many elected candidates as they have in the winning set, and at least one voter has approved more. Take the following example with 500 voters and 2 to elect:

    150 voters: AC
    100 voters: AD
    140 voters: BC
    110 voters: BD

    AB and CD are the only two electable sets for a PR method. In either case every voter will have one elected candidate. PAV and welfarist methods in general would regard them as the same because they just look at number of candidates elected for a voter.

    However, under AB each elected candidate is has been approved by 250 voters. Under CD, it's 290 for C and 210 for D. AB is therefore more proportional than CD, and certainly the result I would prefer. But then you could have:

    150 voters: AC
    100 voters: AD
    140 voters: BC
    110 voters: BD
    1 voter: C
    1 voter: D

    So unless AB's win over CD in the previous example was just of a tie-break nature, AB should still win here. But under the Pareto criterion above, CD must win. I regard this as unsatisfactory.

    The four main criteria I look for in the Holy Grail are:

    Perfect Representation in the Limit (the primary PR criterion I use, which does not disqualify Sainte-Laguë/Webster)
    Strong Monotonicity (so an extra approval should count in favour of a candidate rather than merely not against them and not just as a tie-break measure)*
    Independence of Irrelevant Ballots
    Independence of Universally Approved Candidates

    *Phragmén, while monotonic, fails strong monotonicity. E.g. two to elect:

    1: AB
    1: AC

    It regards all results (AB, AC, BC) as equally good other than possibly in a tie-break (despite A's universal support). This makes a difference in the following example:

    99: AB
    99: AC
    1: B
    1: C

    Phragmén prefers BC in this case, which does not seem right. Electing sequentially avoids this obviously, but examples can easily be found where electing sequentially does not save it from a bad result.

    Anyway, my criteria may be incompatible, in a deterministic method at least. COWPEA Lottery passes them all but is non-deterministic. Optimised PAV Lottery might also pass as well, but this is unproven as far as I am aware.

    Pretty much everything I have discussed here is discussed in detail in my non-peer-reviewed arXiv paper on COWPEA and COWPEA Lottery. I think it's at least worth a look. Arguably the most exciting part is the section on COWPEA v Optimised PAV as the ultimate in cardinal PR for cases where there are no limits to the number and weight of elected candidates.

    posted in Proportional Representation
  • RE: STLR - Score Than Leveled Runoff might not be too complex for voters

    Using score ratios is always a bad idea. It only makes sense (as with utility scores) to look at the absolute difference between scores. If someone scores three candidates 0, 1, 2, then they are equidistant. To see the 1 as infinitely more than the 0 is bad voting method behaviour.

    It would also be insane if (under a 0 to 5 ballot) if someone scoring two candidates 5 and 1 had less voting power in the run-off than someone scoring them 1 and 0.

    posted in Single-winner
  • RE: The Alaskan Top Four Model & iEBs

    @gregw said in The Alaskan Top Four Model & iEBs:

    @toby-pereira said in The Alaskan Top Four Model & iEBs:

    I'm not sure in practice how the results of the Excess Method would differ from SPAV, but I think its complexity counts against it. And considering this is just to narrow down the field, rather than get the best proportional result, I don't think it's probably necessary.

    Thank you for the advice, your point is well taken.

    For a Round 1 vote, I am leaning to a Webster version of SPAV and STAR for Round 2, the general election.

    I saw that SPAV and STAR are listed as failing Participation on the Comparison of Electoral Systems wikipedia page.
    Could those failures be a problem in these two applications?
    Am I paying too much attention to the criterion lists?

    Participation is a very difficult criterion to pass. SPAV fails it, but I think non-sequential PAV passes it. However, it might be computationally unfeasible, and probably not the best method for this particular application anyway. I think sequential PR methods pretty much all fail participation (apart from perhaps non-deterministic ones), so you might just have to accept it.

    For the final round, score and approval both pass participation, so you could select one of them. Approval is generally considered a good method by most people, whether or not is it their absolute favourite.

    posted in Advocacy and Current Events
  • RE: The Alaskan Top Four Model & iEBs

    @gregw said in The Alaskan Top Four Model & iEBs:

    @toby-pereira

    Both SPAV Sequential proportional approval voting and the Excess Method
    The Excess Method: A Multiwinner Approval Voting Procedure to Allocate Wasted Votes
    would work well in narrow down the field in large elections.

    SPAV is a lot easier to count and explain and should work quite well.

    The Excess Method adds calculations after the election of each candidate to distribute the seat winning candidate's excess approvals. This will, at least in theory, better represent the will of the voters. With the Excess Method, voters could approve all the candidates they like with no concern for strategy or temptation to tactical vote.

    A difficult decision. Do you have a dog in this race?

    I'm not sure in practice how the results of the Excess Method would differ from SPAV, but I think its complexity counts against it. And considering this is just to narrow down the field, rather than get the best proportional result, I don't think it's probably necessary.

    posted in Advocacy and Current Events
  • RE: Symmetric Quantile-Normalized Score

    As with the previous version of this, I do ultimately think this method is going to be somewhat Borda-like, with all the problems that it entails, including terrible burial behaviour and poor clone behaviour.

    Edit - I suppose my main question is: In practice what would this method do differently from Borda to make it better?

    posted in New Voting Methods and Variations
  • RE: The Alaskan Top Four Model & iEBs

    I've read through this thread a bit more now. So we first want an election (with potentially quite a lot of candidates standing), where we select four candidates to go into round 2 for the election to determine the winner.

    If there might be a lot of candidates standing in round 1, then to keep it simple, I would definitely recommend some form approval voting. However, under normal approval voting there is the possibility of the top four being blocked out by clones, so it might make sense to use a sequential proportional method. SPAV, the sequential version of PAV, I think would be ideal for this. It shouldn't be hard to calculate when done sequentially (in response to Jack).

    PAV-based methods often aren't recommended for proportional elections because PAV isn't exactly proportional and has some failure cases. However, I don't see that as a problem here. This isn't meant to be an exactly proportional election. It's just to prevent multiple clones appearing on the final ballot. (S)PAV has better monotonicity properties than most other proportional methods - e.g. Phragmén or quota-based methods. SPAV also has a simple algorithm. Phragmén wouldn't be awful for this either, but I wouldn't recommend a method that deals with quotas.

    Then for the final ballot, it's a case of what's your favourite single-winner method. And that's the big debate.

    posted in Advocacy and Current Events